|
Peter Singer:
Equal Consideration For All
Peter Singer's approach
to animal liberation does not assume that animals have inherent rights,
but rather that the interests of animals should be given their due consideration.
Although there are similarities between humans and other animals, there
are also many differences in abilities and interests. It is not expected
that humans and nonhumans should be treated in exactly the same way; the
nature of the being must be taken into account.
Singer argues that,
even among humans, the concept of equality is not that of an actual equality
of attributes. In fact, intellect, physical strength, moral capacity,
and a host of other attributes vary enormously within our species. Equality
must refer to an equal consideration of human interests rather
than to some absolute equality, which clearly does not exist. The interests
of two given human beings might be quite similar or very different, but
in fairness their interests should be given equal consideration. This
is not to say that one interest may not be reasonably evaluated as more
important than another, but rather that no interests should be discounted
unfairly. Now there is no moral or rational reason for not extending such
a consideration of interests to nonhumans as well. This fact forms a foundation
for Singer's arguments for animal liberation.
Singer's philosophy
is essentially preference utilitarianism. Such utilitarianism combines
the equal consideration of interests with the idea that the right action
is the one which yields the greatest satisfaction of interests over frustration
of interests for all those involved. Although this measurement might be
difficult in some situations, utilitarianism generally has the positive
effect of preventing a situation from becoming too lopsided as far as
the interests of the involved parties are concerned. Presently, the human
exploitation of animals is a very lopsided situation, where even the trivial
interests of humans usually prevail over the most basic interests of animals,
such as the desire to live or the avoidance of pain and suffering.
Many humans see no
problem with the exploitation of other animals since humans are clearly
intellectually superior. But Singer poses the question, "If possessing
a higher degree of intelligence does not entitle one human to use another
for his own ends, how can it entitle humans to exploit nonhumans?"
(Animal Rights and Human Obligations, 1989) From a moral standpoint,
it simply does not follow that the possession of certain abilities should
allow one to discount the interests of another. Hence, the belief in human
superiority is no basis for routinely discounting the interests of nonhumans,
whether or not they come into conflict with human interests.
Singer uses racism
and sexism as examples of why it is wrong to promote the interests of
one group over another simply because the perpetrator is a member of the
favored group. Racism and sexism are not wrong only because all races
and sexes are equal in abilities and achievements. In fact, a little research
shows that there are some significant differences. Whether all such differences
can be attributed entirely to environment is unclear but not really relevant
to the issues of racism or sexism. For if one race or sex were inherently
superior in one way or another, that would not morally entitle the superior
race or sex to routinely discount the interests of the inferior. In reality,
sometimes "might makes right," but neither morality nor reason
can support such a stance. As an analog to racism and sexism, speciesism
involves favoring the interests of one's own species over another. Speciesism
is extremely widespread among humans, who routinely discount the fundamental
interests of nonhumans to satisfy the often trivial interests of humans.
Singer points to the consumption of animal products as a clear example.
Under the modern agricultural system, billions of animals live under horrendous
conditions much or all of their lives, only to be slaughtered so that
humans can experience the taste of animal flesh, for which humans have
no nutritional requirement. Arguably, this mistreatment and killing of
animals for human pleasure is speciesism at its worst.
Still, in an attempt
to justify their exploitation of animals perhaps, some humans continue
to argue that animals just do not possess the mental capacity to live
the meaningful lives that humans live. The wealth of literature to the
contrary should eliminate such notions, but even allowing for such a belief
in the limited capacities of animals, one of Singer's arguments is stunning:
For if we would like to justify the exploitation of animals, say in scientific
research, due to a supposed lack of mental capacity, then a non-speciesist
argument for not exploiting severely brain-damaged or otherwise mentally
handicapped humans in a similar fashion does not exist. Is it morally
acceptable to subject the less fortunate humans to medical experimentation
or product testing? If not, then exploiting a nonhuman of similar mental
capacity in a similar way is also immoral, and outright speciesist.
Even though Singer does
not strictly support inherent animal rights, his convincing arguments
and frequent appeal to the lay reader have resulted in his great popularity
among animal rights advocates. By far, his most famous work is Animal
Liberation (1975, 1990). Some of his other books include Practical
Ethics (1993), How Are We to Live? (1995), and Ethics Into
Action (1998).
Copyright
© 2000 TheVegetarianSite, All Rights Reserved
|